- ...P1
- Thanks to Andrea Veatch, Norma Mendoza-Denton, Jonathan
Haidt, Hadass Sheffer, William T. Reynolds, Shirley Brice-Heath, Mark
Keavney, Victor Raskin, Henry Gleitman, Amy Carrell and others for
helpful discussions. Thanks also for the useful comments of three
anonymous reviewers. Most of this work was carried out with the
financial support of a Mellon Postdoctoral Fellowship at Stanford
University.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... Aristotle2
- Aristotle's Comedy is lost to
us, since approximately 800 A.D.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... many3
- My bibliography
file contains 619 entries at the most recent count.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... not.4
- The theory does not have a behaviorist focus,
since it centers on internal subjective interpretations and the
resulting internal states rather than on external stimulus and
observable response characteristics. Behavior is evidence for the
theory, but (with present methods) unobservables are its defining
elements. Similarly, until not long ago, the theory of atoms was one
of unobservable elements, supported by observable evidence.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... order.5
- Kierkegaard, for
example, wrote that humor communicates on an ethical/moral level.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... more.6
- This fact corresponds to Wyer &
Collins' (1992) Proposition 8, that cognitive
elaboration increases humor. See discussion below.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... eliminated.7
- This may seem reminiscent
of a Freudian, or one might say, hydraulic view of emotions, but it
can just as easily be considered as a process of reasoning in which
multiple hypotheses are initially entertained at once, then
insufficiently plausible or emotionally compelling ones are eliminated
on further consideration.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... prolonged.8
- This explains
Proposition 8 of Wyer & Collins (1992), which makes the role of
further elaboration a central tenet or proposition of their theory.
However, this observation is a consequence, not an axiom, of the
present theory.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... set-up.9
- Other interpretations of this joke are also possible,
including one in which the punchline reveals the violation that Jesus
should be concerned about such mundane things as seeing Peter's house
when he's dying. I believe I did not see this interpretation when I
first encountered this joke; at the same time it is entirely possible
for people to laugh at different things in the same joke. The
existence of one valid interpretation doesn't refute the existence of
another valid interpretation, if both can stand on their own merits.
The present argument is based on the mere existence of a valid
interpretation with an N+V ordering and thus does not require all
other interpretations to be invalid.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... humor.10
- Kierkegaard (1941/1846:446-7),
Koestler (1964), Nerhardt (1976),
Forabosco (1992), Wyer & Collins (1992)
are some authors who propose a crucial role for
incongruity or absurdity.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... question11
- Thanks to Mark Keavney for pointing this out
to me.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... beginning.12
- This
explanation for the repetition effect is overlooked by Wyer & Collins
(1992), where instead it is the reduced possibility for further
cognitive elaboration in repetitions that is used to explain their
reduced humor potential. This despite the fact that comprehension
difficulty is an axiom of their theory, and despite the fact that the
explanation is invalid: The fiftieth Monty Python movie rerun remains
funny to some not because there are further cognitive elaborations
discovered, but because the violations and the dead-pan normality
interpretations remain convincing.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ...
cases.13
- A comparative phonetic study of the acoustic
properties of the different vocalizations in crying, laughing, and
gasping in pain is called for. What acoustical properties make them
distinctively identifiable? How can they be convincingly synthesized
or accurately recognized by machine? Are there learned,
culture-specific, communicatively important features of these
vocalizations? What is shared (and what can vary) among all the very
different vocalizations that are identifiably of one type or the
other?
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... attitudes.14
- As much is implied by
discussion in the speech communication literature recommending humor
as a tool for speakers, teachers, and others who wish to communicate
effectively (e.g., Tacey, 1967).
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... have:15
- In doing ethnographic or other
fieldwork to explore such questions, for example, one might also ask
subjects what offends them, but that seems a more dicey method, since
it is not a good thing to offend one's informants. Further, this tool
is useful in everyday situations.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.