The logic of biological evolution rests on tautologies.
D'oh! I guess actually I didn't say anything there. Just another tautology.
But tautologies have a peculiar force. If their categories are actually real and undeniable, you can't deny them, or argue with them; inexorable, they hold us all helpless. Therefore submit, brave heart, and see what you may learn! Here are some, in the world of evolution, where organisms can survive and reproduce.
If an organism survives and reproduces then it survives and reproduces. H.
If it dies then it dies.
But, why and how death itself evolved sure seems like a non-tautological question. Does understanding something mean reducing it to tautologies? Consider: is death an evolutionary accelerator? Adult necessarily outcompetes zygote, fetus, child, even immature adult. H. Hence without death under population constraints there is no room for the young; the species is selected for the past instead of the future, and hence could not adapt as well to change. H. Having reduced the matter to tautologies, have we understood it better? I think so. Having invented death, the new immature must merely survive its competition with the old mature in order to provide for evolutionary success under change. Hence we also have selection pressure for child-supportiveness, even for parental love.If one dies before it reproduces, then none of its descendants actually descend, nor exist, nor multiply. Its branch in the tree of life is cut off. Does this say anything? No. H. It's just another way of saying the same thing.
If organisms with some feature die out of a species, then that feature has been "selected against". A definition: H. If the organisms carrying a feature reproduce before they die, and their descendants do too, then their branches in the tree of life continue forward generation after generation, and if there are many, then there are many; if these contrast with others in that the others without that feature don't, then the feature is "selected for". Definition. H.
Survival and reproduction are required for past, mortal, life to continue into the future. H.
When a community with internal relationships has members surviving and reproducing before death and its new young members come to participate in maintaining those relationships, the community itself survives and reproduces. Another definition.
The world in which life exists and continues into the indefinite future is a world of sufficient resources, energy, and time or stability, for life, at least for now.
I still don't think I've said anything yet. Just like 1=1.
Ye progressives, consider conservatism in nature. Nature is basically 100% conservative! As conservative as possible, it will repeat the same thing and infinitely, forever, completely, identically without variation, forever and ever and ever and ever. After all it was so costly to get to the point of any kind of functionality at all that we have to just hang on it and be sure that we keep it otherwise it’s gonna be really hard to get there again.
Ye conservatives, notice: On the other hand there is an element of nature which is exploratory and progressive and seeking functional innovation and trying to make the world a better place or at least its capabilities better. But that has to be an extremely low cost endeavor from the perspective of nature and life itself. So yes we do have random mutational innovation exploring all kinds of adjacent alternatives. But we have it in the context of an exponential explosive population growth. And there is explosive exponential population growth and it doesn’t matter if some crappy mutations happen and heck most of them are going to die before they even get born and most of the rest are going to die before they live a day and most of those that survive are going to die before they live to reproduction age, and some of those are going to have children that die. But it doesn’t matter because everybody else is having kids like crazy and we’re having an exponential population growth.
So the way it must work is that there must be two filters which Darwin doesn’t seem to recognize, does he?: two not one. The first one is survivability of a mutation: suppose you have a change, and it makes it a new type of different, slightly different organism. Well there’s an immediate filter of, Did it survive (to reproduce) at all? Is it a survivable mutation? Is this a form of variation that the species can even tolerate while surviving? Forget about environmental change putting pressure on our population, is this change even survivable? That’s the first filter.
Then in between the first filter and the second filter there’s this continuing exponential population explosion thing going on and what it means is that everybody’s getting many, many, many grandchildren so that even a crappy, barely survivable, but not really very usable mutation will suddenly be distributed in a species in numbers where, you know, after 10 generations of merely doubling it’s 1024 organisms and that’s probably enough to form the core of a new species if it happens to be the only subgroup that survives The Kataklysm that comes after. Do you see the selection phase in phase 2 has to select on species which, after it killed all the ones that don’t have the advantageous feature, has to leave enough of them for them as a group to be as messy and variable and robust as a whole species is. It’s not just, Poof, here's a new mutation, Do you have a mutation that is selected for? -- because then that's saying everybody else dies and there’s only one there which got the mutation and that means there’s no species! So you need enough carriers to have a core group at the very least.
OK, so then you have this survivable feature across some generations and there’s been doubling so you have 1000 organisms in a species of say a million or whatever, then comes the cataclysm.
In the cataclysm the feature is selected for or against or ignored. That's phase 2 of selection.
Make sense? Makes sense to me. A logical restatement:
A species is an environmentally compatible (H), practically self-sustaining (H) community (H) of organism-specifying information, comprising a set of fixed and variable genes, the variable ones comprising a set of mutually substitutable alleles within the gene (H) such that organisms each contain a copy of each fixed gene and a copy of one allele for each variable gene (H).
Sexual reproduction mixes randomly-chosen halves of each of two parents, independently functional gene sets, to create each descendant, a new individual, a new functional gene set (H, H, H, H). After a few generations of reproductive mixture along with death of forebears in a living species, the genes are mixed around in different bodies but they are the same total set of genes and alleles modulo mutations (H). These practically useful information units depend on each other (within the environment) to survive into the indefinite future (H). If some combination of genes and alleles happen to systematically interfere with survival of its carriers, then the community will drift in the direction of having fewer of that combination within it (H), eventually none -- and only if the interference is faster than the exponential growth of the species population (H).
There is a story-scheme concept to help us think about it. You might consider a happy ending and a sad ending as two substitutable sentences in a short story, for example. Like a web page with a pull-down menu for "Ending", which inserts the selection for that substitutable subsection. One story schema could have many substitutable sub-sections, and a limited list of items that may be substituted in there.
In the gene representation, the fixed genes are like fixed framing sentences in this story scheme, and they surround slots where the differences in the individual stories are isolated: everyone's story has these same framing bits. The alleles, which substitute in as the values of a gene with variable contents, are like the mutually substitutable sentences that go into the slots in the story. Then each organism's information is like a single, fully-specified story, containing both the fixed parts, and a full set of selections from the substituteable sets. The living population, which embodies the species, is the entire set of life-specifying stories currently selected within all the current living organisms, and the species itself is this sort of abstract pond of information, carried by the group of organisms, each being a bearer of its own copy of shared bits of the story. The fixed bits are shared with all, and the variable bits are shared with some, of the other members of the species. The species itself, you might say, is a kind of abstraction, which includes the happy ending AND the sad ending, both at once. It is the commonality across the set of all those stories or narrative subselections. This story or information structure is defined in biochemistry by the actual DNA choice points and actual choices chosen there, and is defined in bitter logic by their compatibility with and enhancement of mutual or shared survival. Without successful, survival-and-reproduction-compatible cooperation among these informational units, the many choices cannot individually survive, so mutual compatibility is a filtering requirement on the choices and their interactions. H.
If a life form does not have systems in it which tend to, nay, which reliably, make it survive and reproduce in its environment, then it won't (H) -- because survival over evolutionary time is an excellent proxy for this kind of reliability. Therefore effective survival and reproduction mechanisms are necessary for an organism and will be present in any evolved species (H). In general if a species has (a) evolved specialized anatomy for a function, it would seem to have (b) a reliable solution for that problem and to hold it (c) high on the priority list for the species to carry out that function. Thus air, food, and reproduction each have all three of (a) and (b) and (c).
We are moving in the direction of what you, I, and humans all care about.
But it is not a happy story getting there. In cases where a survival-connected outcome is only loosely predictable from a certain stochastic or variable mechanism (which produces survival in a given generation at a probability of, say, P where P<<1), the carriers of the mechanism will only loosely survive (with probability P) in one generation. Over a few -- or for a subtle effect over many -- generations without otherwise increased reproduction, that total probability (Pn) will approach zero (H). Functional logic is harsh and controlling, when the tautologies of evolution impose it on life.
From this follows the prioritization of survival before reproduction where separable: you can reproduce another day if you survive first, but if not, then not (H).
We can generalize over many priorities.
Prioritization is itself an evolutionary selection target, in which mechanisms or prioritizations are selected for on the basis of both correctness and effectiveness. To be correct, the prioritization mechanism must choose the right priority -- one that further enables survival and reproduction or the relevant, predictive, subordinate outcomes. H. Multiple alternatives may be right enough to suffice, while some alternatives might really interfere; therefore to be effective, the mechanism must prevent interfering alternative priorities from being carried out. H.
If survival depends on multiple subordinate outcomes, and each subordinate outcome has an evolved, effective mechanism to satisfy it but which cannot operate simultaneously and at equal priority with others, then the competitive prioritization of all the mechanisms (for their respective outcomes) and suppression of alternatives to the chosen priority must be done by a competent meta-mechanism, which is able to make and enforce a detailed rank ordering according to system state or circumstances, so as to orchestrate the few survivable and reproducing outcomes reliably (H).
Maslow's hierarchy of needs, the Hindu chakra system, the Freudian plural id, the hormonally-defined (and -governed) subpersonalities, and the at least hypothalamic system for choosing which subpersonality must be in charge when: these are perhaps expressions or, roughly, homomorphisms of a single, of one and the same, of this functional logic and prioritization constraint set, imposed on complex life by the tautologies of life. Of course survival first. Respiration, temperature, rest/sleep, sustenance, have their nonlinear hierarchy of systemic control, which may derive from the duration of time you can survive without that particular homeostatic requirement being met. The sooner you die without some requirement being met, the higher the priority and the more rigid the enforcement. This seems like raw tautology, but we now have separable mechanisms linking to separable functional outcomes: were it not so, were it instead that mechanisms were not linked to outcomes, then those fatal outcomes would fail to be defended against, and at some greater probability would occur, and over generations those life forms will not last long, as the chances multiply. So long-term evolutionary survival statistically implies (over tens, thousands or millions of generations it more and more categorically implies) strong and reliable, carefully, calibratedly, mutually prioritizing, mechanisms to defend against each of the various standard modes of practical failure, of death or non-reproduction.
This is so not just at the level of conscious, linguistic, supposedly rational humanity, for which internal symbol representation and manipulation and, for example, discrete planning processes are axiomatic among cognitive scientists. It is even true at the level of paramecia, of single-celled mobile creatures (and in recent news even at the level of groups of mitochondria within a cell).
Because if the life form doesn't have mechanisms that reliably produce surviving, reproducing outcomes, which are discrete outcomes, then it won't continue to evolve, but will drop out even from the very dustbin of history into the vacuum of non-existence, as something that never even needed to have been tried as an experiment.
A scientist's job therefore includes the cognitive scientist's job.
Is this just the mental masturbation of overexcited grammarians? Or is it a necessary level of description of the functional logic of what actually ends up happening within the context of discrete, evolutionarily unavoidable and potentially bitter outcomes. I say the latter. Because if you can't get that logical system right in describing a biological system, then you don't understand why the thing is able to actually survive and reproduce, and more fundamentally even if you know the physics, the chemistry, the biochemistry, the cell biology, every detail of every subsystem, you still don't have any handle on WHY it survives or not: you don't understand it. System understanding depends on the cognitive scientist's modelling. H! Just try to prove me wrong.
So, what are these discrete categories and the motivational frames of organismal existence, what is the rank ordering of priority, what is the logic controlling their relations and community of interest, and the communications or interactions they must have, if only in sharing to an internal prioritizer/controller mechanism their several concerns and status reports or awarenesses for it to mediate or sort?: A scientist must also describe these discrete, cognitive behaviors within the functional logic that applies to them. For if the organism doesn't follow, doesn't implement, that logic, it will shortly be gone. Thus I make room for, I demand!, cognitive modeling of animal behavior, not just of humans or human language, but at least down to the level of protozoa.
This is the problem, the logical problem of evolution: burble up resistance-capable tracks and motor, or be swept clean off the cliff into oblivion. Given the bulldozer and the cliff, either you do, or you don't.
The attack direction and the resistance capability are opposing logical forces. A bulldozer’s direction may be any imaginable or unimaginable thing in the space of physical possibility, but its approach is a logical bit: presence or absence, and its response is a logical bit, capability-versus-challenge, presence or absence. Then both bits apply stochastically to every congealed blobbet in the gene puddle and to opportunistic occurrence of bulldozer shoves, and over evolutionary time there is either a clean cliff or a counterbalancing capability with its counterbalanced challenge.
Understanding both sides and their relation is the job of the logician of evolution. It's basically a characterization of the nature of the dimension, the abstraction which is to say the functional interaction in the challenge and response, and what function is carried out when the challenge is raised and when it is met. It's actually quite abstract.
Said logician's job is to find and define the dimension, to reduce it to a bit, the yes no of a functional actual challenge or threat, and and of its functional challenge-response, the actual functional response, also down to a bit. More and less are good to think about but the job is not to do that first, but Later, because more or Less of WHAT is the first question.
For example, it seems that the driven-personality quality of people, as we arguably are, is a quality equally driven and necessary in the least watery wiggler. If an organism isn't driven, doesn't coalign all its available and useful resources, you might say, with all its might, in circumstances that threaten it, to drive toward whatever motivations can be ascribed to it (in my sense, "cognitively") for its (necessary) survival, then obviously it may, considering it as its species as a whole, rather more frequently fail to survive. The tautologies apply, and bye-bye. Even a slight probabilistic slip between mechanism and the survival it relates to will lead over a million generations to obliteration. 0.9991,000,000 is an excellent approximation of zero.
Consider attention itself, consisting in the continual reassessing of priorities and of situational awareness tending to inform those priorities. Attention would seem to be a highly valued early evolutionary achievement. For otherwise rapidly changing conditions would be fatal, and yes the Tautologies of Evolution apply.
Similarly, integrated behavioral control, whereby a single target of action is aimed at, since one can hardly hit two targets at a time much less more, would also seem highly valued, evolutionary speaking. For if competing incompatible priorities are allowed to remain unresolved in a circumstance of potential action, no target may be obtained, an outcome likely to be, or evidently, evolutionarily inferior to one where the most important single target was actually aimed at and acted towards or into being.
I'm not saying mechanisms are the same between humans and protozoa. Mechanisms might be different for the same functional outcome, if new ones might be evolved that are as good or better, but the functional logic is the same, from paramecia to people. Functionally one could say those mechanisms perform the same task, indeed, are the same system. They live in the same functional box, subject to the same logic. No efficient designer, neither Ockham nor hurried evolution itself, would fail to reuse the contents, by the way, so why we should think we are so different from worms with our special uniquely human characteristics of attention, spatial awareness, integrated action control (a.k.a. Will), I don't know. I don't think we are.
I have argued that the unarguable tautologies and harsh constraints of evolution impose a symbolic, discrete logic on successfully evolved (all living) organisms. From what may evolve, I turn next to when things may evolve, in what order.
We are given a descendant species with some set of novel characteristics N as compared with the shared set of characteristics Sh among the other species in the genus. Are we perhaps entirely unable to reason about the sequence by which the N characteristics evolved? There may be no archeological or DNA data on the question.
For example, what came first, eyes or blue eyes? Blue eyes couldn't have come first in the sequence of evolution, because you can't have blue eyes without having eyes, whereas you can have eyes and even light sensitive patches without irises entirely, without having blue eyes.
Or, what came first, fingers or fingernails? Perhaps it's a failure of scientific imagination, imagining fingernails on something other than fingers, then growing fingers out underneath them, but that sure doesn't make sense to me.
If you can see two features as logically dependent in this way, it would seem to require the dependent feature to follow, or at least not to separately precede, the independent feature. A fuzzy thinker might propose an argument noticing a dependency where an opposite argument may later be found, in that case logic may seem to waver. But logic is universally reliable, for those that can use it. And true logical dependency requires that one feature not independently precede another, and we can use that to absolutely rule out certain orderings of observed features in the evolution of a species. Such a conclusion is not a matter of observation, of contingency, or of probability, but of Logic itself, which precedes the Big Bang itself and anticipates every true discovery ever made, since each must always be logically possible, though noone may have ever noticed, nor may ever.
Is this the limit of our powers? I don't think so, though my professional evolutionary biologist friends seem to act as though all evolutionary reasoning not conducted by their own PhD students or subject to their PhD defense cross-examinations is intellectually substanceless and can be assumed to be morally perverse. I exaggerate slightly. Job security does not give you the right to shut everyone else up with attacks ad hominem or otherwise than based in reason.
Suppose a certain result associated with N2, such as a measureable average, or a population frequency of some feature, etc., is, say, some positive X% more likely to be reproduced or enhanced with another feature, N1, precedent and present than without. That is,
P(N1<N2) = P(N2<N1) * (100-X)/100Then what is the likelihood of one ordering N1<N2 versus the other N2<N1? (Here I use "<" for temporal order not relative quantity.) It's not just a single point event in the case of evolutionary time, but an accumulation of more or less probable events across generation after generation for tens and hundreds or thousands of generations. Let AP(o,g) be the accumulated probability of order o across g generations. We have to compare the relative likelihoods of P(N1<N2) occurring g times, versus P(N2<N1) occurring g times. Suppose N2<N1 is taken as the null hypothesis with relative probability 1, then
AP(N1<N2,g) = P(N1<N2)^g / P(N2<N1)^g = P(N1<N2)^g = ((100-X)/100)^g |------| |------| 1 100-X/100Thus, if X is only 5%, meaning that both novel features N1 and N2 could each logically or potentially, precede the other, but there is a 5% advantage in one generation if N1 arrives first, then after only 100 generations,
AP(N1<N2,100) = 0.95^100 = 0.00592, about 1/2 of 1%.In this way, small relative fitness differences may justify strong reasoning about the ordering of novel features in the evolution of a species.
Restating: the full-sequence likelihood of the opposite order is (100%-X%)^G with G the number of generations. If X is 5%, and G is 100 generations, then the likelihood ratio of N1 preceding N2 versus N2 preceding N1 (which we can use as null hypothesis with likelihood 1^100=1) is 0.95^100 / 1 = 0.0059. In short, a small degree of relative ease of one evolutionary path versus another potentially reordered path may be translated to an enormously strong argument, from a statistical perspective, for that sequence being the easy rather than the even ever-so-slightly-more-difficult path.
This actually gives us a lot of leverage on the problem. It's not impossible to find relative ease differences, possibly-small impacts on how one feature supports the functionality of another feature.
My favorite, Aquatic Ape features: Bipedality; Voluntary breathing control (necessarily preceding speech); Love or tolerance of swimming; Body Hairlessnes; Long head hair. Control of fire. Diet changes. Long distance running. A huge heel. Body temperature regulation by sweating. Ability to swim. Fear of snakes, of sharks, of the various kinds of unknown. Compared with chimps, more acidic stomachs, more ketotic metabolism, less chimp-like raw-fiber digestion, preference for fatter (large) prey. Changes in disgust sensation; Stench, a.k.a. stinky smell sensitivity. Eclectic carnivory; obesity. Tool use. Conversation. Sign systems. Language. Joketelling. Storytelling. Lying. Theory of mind and emotions. Clothing. Multi-sensory integrated spatial awareness. Bodily Decoration. Art. Religion. Moralizing. The Lecture. Admiration. Scapegoating. Mob violence. Male gang formation, predation, rape, war. Multiplication of dominance hierarchies. Gender contrast in anatomy and strength relating to fight and flight contexts. Oversized male larynx. Lowered larynx such that breathing and swallowing are not simultaneously possible. Female relative lack of sense of direction (?). Female sexual attraction to funny males. Cryptic fertility of females. Female orgasm. Commerce and exchange. Lying. Negotiation. Subpopulation variation in melanin concentration, eye color, height, strength, task endurance. Sexual anatomy & physiology peculiarities: excess size, glans skin furrowing, glans shelf, mobile foreskin, extended duration coitus, semen deposit volume and viscosity and viscosity change over short time periods (these support a gang rape theory of (?pre-?)human reproduction). Subcutaneous body fat distribution. Literacy. Architecture. Internal storytelling about self as a method for social and emotional regulation. Various subspeciation changes: more vs less curly hair differences, the Asian epicanthic fold, the northern european adaptations for low-light survival despite metabolic need for light-requiring vitamin D3: translucent skin to make the most of little sunlight and lactose tolerance to get D3 from milk sources. (To develop a long list of shared-with-chimps evolutionary traits, look for a minute at the hairless chimp videos on YouTube.)My own personality is MB ET, an extrovert thinker: I like to talk and think, which are nearly the same thing for me; I accept that being wrong is part of the process. I'm happy to be wrong! If a logical argument shows a stronger effect in the opposite order, fine. And for two events there can only be only three orderings, before, after, and overlapping, and as I've shown we can legitimately reason from one order being a little easier than the other, already it's a strong argument given the exponential filter of evolution. So it's worth making stabs in the dark, if they seem reasonable, because that starts things off. Stating clearly an initial, possibly wrong position allows it to be contradicted by something better, and thus can progress be made.
Taking this obnoxious yet humble approach, my own view is: